Ontological discussions around the concept of species are as old as biology itself; yet, these discussions largely bypass our school lessons. In school, we only discuss different ways to recognize species (biospecies, ecospecies, morphospecies, and chronospecies). My viewpoint is, therefore, not meant to be another philosophical treatise on the species problem; it is only meant to make the problem briefly and concisely understandable for students and teachers. We should not be afraid to debate ontological questions with our students. In the context of a scientific education, a clear and defined language is essential. We should not use the term “species” without facing its ontology at least once.
In the minds of students, the concepts of species and evolution somehow belong together, but few know exactly how. “Evolution amounts to speciation, that is, to the emergence of qualitatively novel organisms” (Mahner and Bunge 1997) [
2]. Evolution is driven by random mutations and natural selection; the latter is an individual–environment interaction. Individuals are selected (survival of the fittest) and populations (individuals with binding relations) evolve. A species is a natural kind (of equivalent organisms), but step by step: To ask students what a species is always has something rhetorical about it. The rote answer comes all too quickly, learned by heart without ever thinking about it: “A species is a reproductive community of populations (reproductively isolated from others), which occupies a specific niche in nature” (Mayr 1982) [
3]. Even if several objections could be raised against this “definition”, it is maybe the best-known statement in modern biology. “In fact, it is an indicator hypothesis: it does not tell us what a biospecies is but how to recognize it, namely by observing reproduction or else by failing to observe the latter. Neither [mutual] reproduction nor [sexual] isolation are defining properties of a species but, at best, properties of organisms that may be used as symptoms of the latters’ membership in a particular species. In other words, two organisms do not belong to the same species because they mate and reproduce, but they only are able to do so because they belong to the same species” (Mahner and Bunge 1997) [
2]. (I had already cited this paragraph in Müller et al. (2007) [
4] in the context of an original paper (on ITS2 secondary structures and distinguishing species), but, with this viewpoint here, I would like to give my students (especially the prospective biology teachers) a more general and shorter overview (a handout) of the species problem.) I was very lucky to have had good teachers (I actually met Ernst Mayr and Martin Mahner); they asked questions, and did not necessarily provide answers: “Do two people look alike because they are twins or are they twins because they look alike?” I learned to distinguish between recognition and explanation. Biospecies, chronospecies, morphospecies, ecospecies, etc., all those concepts are merely correlated indicator hypotheses. They only enable us to recognize species. Such indicator hypotheses are not definitions and they do not tell us anything about what a species is. The latter is an ontological question and there are two competing concepts, SAI and SANK. SAI (species as individuals) considers a species as an individual carrier of properties; the species evolves. Individuals in relation to species are not elements, but are degraded to an illogical part–whole relationship. SANK (species as natural kinds) considers (and this sounds more logical to me) the individuals as carriers of properties; here, populations (i.e., individuals with binding relations) evolve. Accordingly, species—individuals with equivalent properties—are natural kinds (classes of equivalent organisms), and thus, species are conceptual. SAI- or SANK-concepts allow the definition of species; they explain species as real or conceptual! On this subject, with only a few exceptions, there is little easy to read literature for students or teachers. However, I strongly recommend the book “Multicellular Animals—A New Approach to the Phylogenetic Order in Nature—Volume I” by Peter Ax (1996) [
5]; and with respect to
Homo sapiens, species concepts are excellently discussed by Walter Sudhaus (2020) [
6]. In practice, biologists are not or only rarely confronted with SAI and/or SANK, i.e., in practice biologists work with the above-mentioned indicator hypotheses. Nevertheless, the ontological question about the nature of species is, in my opinion, relevant, particularly for teaching. The biospecies concept from Ernst Mayr was considered as a definition and was accused of having confused the reason for recognition with the reason for explanation—a classical SAI/SANK debate, and I was right in the middle. Do two people look alike because they are twins or are they twins because they look alike? Two organisms do not belong to the same species because they mate and reproduce, but they only are able to do so because they belong to the same species. What is a species? Sometimes teaching questions enlightens students more than giving them answers. Most biology teachers unfortunately have no opinion on whether species are real or conceptual, simply because they have never been taught the question themselves, but rather one answer they still pass on to their students today, learned by heart without ever thinking about it. How to teach about what is a species? We should teach about what a definition is, about cladistics, about what is real (what is reality) and what is science all about—questions and not just answers learned by rote. Teach problem awareness, follow up questions and the consequences of answers. The “species” concept in school science (including a literature survey) has been extensively reviewed by Nyléhn und Ødegaard (2018) [
7]; however, an ontological debate plays only a subordinate role here. From a pedagogical point of view, do not be afraid to venture into a philosophical excursion in your biology class. Use scenarios, associations, small group activities and context clues. Put the term “species” into context and/or create a story around the term “species”. Instruct your students to write sentences using the term “species” and/or read sentences with the word “species” embedded, e.g., talk about “species” extinction, about invasive “species”, about distinguishing “species”, etc. As a philosophical exercise, use the twin example as described above and/or just ask your students who can swim, dance, laugh, or cry? Can a “species” do anything at all? Is it possible to examine a “species”? Do we need at all the term “species”, or do we need even more terms for the different meanings of the term? Concerning the latter, for further reading and for an in-depth discussion of natural kinds
sensu lato,
sensu stricto, of more than 30 different species concepts (including ontological and operational species concepts), see Mahner and Bunge (1997) [
2] and/or Zachos (2015) [
8]. Therein also, the historical development, as well as the practical relevance of different species concepts, is thoroughly discussed. The discussion about what a species is will certainly continue. Arguments against my viewpoint you may want to find e.g., in “The reality of species: real phenomena not theoretical objects” by Wilkins (2017) [
9]. I would like to end fairly with one of his questions, “What is a mountain?” and last but not least with a final statement by myself: Not species die but individuals and each is biodiversity worth protecting, the latter I hope we can all agree with.