Mill and Mental Phenomena: Critical Contributions to a Science of Cognition
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. Method and Contents
1.2. What is Cognition?
2. Sociocultural Context
3. Mill’s Vision for Psychology
3.1. Empirical Science of Mind
(Experimentation)…not only enables us to produce a much greater number of variations in the circumstances than nature spontaneously offers, but, also, in thousands of cases, to produce the precise sort of variation which we are in want of for discovering the law of the phenomenon—a service which nature, being constructed on a quite different scheme from that of facilitating our studies, is seldom so friendly as to bestow upon us…When we can produce a phenomenon artificially, we can take it, as it were, home with us, and observe it in the midst of the circumstances with which in all other respects we are accurately acquainted.[1]
In the case of sensations, another distinction has also to be kept in view, which is often confounded, and never without mischievous consequences. This is the distinction between the sensation itself, and the state of the bodily organs which precedes the sensation, and which constitutes the physical agency by which it is produced. One of the sources of confusion on this subject is the division commonly made of feelings into Bodily and Mental. Philosophically speaking, there is no foundation at all for this distinction: even sensations are states of the sentient mind, not states of the body.[1]
Every sensation has for its proximate cause some affectation of the portion of our frame called the nervous system, whether this affectation originate in the action of some external object, or in some pathological condition of the nervous organization itself”.[1]
…that every mental state has a nervous state for its immediate antecedent and proximate cause, though extremely probable, cannot hitherto be said to be proved, in the conclusive manner in which this can be proved of sensations; and even were it certain, yet everyone must admit that we are wholly ignorant of the characteristics of these nervous states; we know not, and at the present have no means of knowing what respect one of them differs from another; and our only mode of studying their succession and co-existences must be by observing the successions and co-existences of the mental states of which they are supposed to be the generators or causes.”.([1], italics added)
The successions, therefore, which obtain among mental phenomena do not admit of being deduced from the physiological laws of our nervous organization; and all real knowledge of them must continue, for a long time at least, if not always, to be sought in direct study, by observation and experiment, of the mental successions themselves.[1]
3.2. Frontiers of Associationism
To establish a relation between mental functions and cerebral conformations, requires not only a parallel system of observations applied to each, but…an analysis of the mental faculties…conducted without any reference to the physical conditions, since the proof of the theory would lie in the correspondence between the division of the brain into organs and that of the mind into faculties, each shown by separate evidence. To accomplish this analysis requires direct psychological study carried to a high pitch of perfection.[23]
3.3. Capacities and Limits of Introspection
The observing and the observed organ are here the same, and its action cannot be pure and natural… In order to observe, your intellect must pause from activity; yet it is this very activity that you want to observe. If you cannot effect the pause, you cannot observe; if you do effect it, there is nothing to observe.[14]
…it might have occurred to M. Comte that a fact may be studied through the medium of memory, not at the very moment of our perceiving it, but the moment after: and this is really the mode in which our best knowledge of our intellectual acts is generally acquired. We reflect on what we have been doing, when the act is past, but when its impression in the memory is still fresh.[23]
We know of our observings and our reasonings, either at the very time, or by memory the moment after; in either case, by direct knowledge, and not (like things done by us in a state of somnambulism) merely by their results([23], italics added)
No mere contemplation of the phenomena, and partition of them by the intellect alone, will of itself accomplish the end we now have in view. Nevertheless, such a mental partition is an indispensable first step…To determine that point (of true cause and effect) we must endeavor to effect a separation of the facts from one another, not in our minds only, but in nature. The mental analysis must take place first.[1]
3.3.1. Divided Attention and Selective Attention
3.3.2. Meta-cognition
4. Discussion
5. Conclusions
Acknowledgements
References
- Mill, J.S. A system of logic. In Excerpt reprinted in A History of Psychology, 3rd ed.; Benjamin, L.T., Ed.; Blackwell Publishing: Malden, MA, USA, 2009; pp. 39–44. [Google Scholar]
- Cognition. Oxford English Dictionary; Oxford University: Oxford, UK, 2012. Available online: http://www.oed.com/view/Entry/35876?redirectedFrom=cognition#eid (accessed on 20 December 2012).
- Chaney, D.W. An overview of the first use of the terms cognition and behavior. Behav. Sci. 2013, 3, 143–153. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walter, S.; Kästner, L. The where and what of cognition: The untenability of cognitive agnosticism and the limits of the Motley Crew Argument. Cogn. Syst. Res. 2012, 13, 12–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stone, T.; Davies, M. Theoretical issues in cognitive psychology. In Cognitive Psychology, 2nd ed.; Braisby, N., Gellatly, A., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Anderson, J.R. Cognitive Psychology and its Implications, 6th ed.; Worth Publishers: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, F. Why we still need a mark of the cognitive. Cogn. Syst. Res. 2010, 11, 324–331. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Damasio, A. Descartes Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain; Penguin Books: New York, NY, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Habibi, D.A. John Stuart Mill and the Ethic of Human Growth; Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Capaldi, N. John Stuart Mill: A Biography; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Mill, J.S. Autobiography. 1873. Available online: http://www.bartleby.com/25/1/ (accessed on 20 December 2012).
- Wilson, F. John Stuart Mill. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2007; Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/mill/ (accessed on 20 December 2012).
- Kuhn, T.S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Comte, A. The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte; Martineau, H., Translator; Calvin Blanchard: New York, NY, USA, 1855. [Google Scholar]
- Gibson, E.J. Has psychology a future? Psychol. Sci. 1994, 5, 69–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moore, T.V. Cognitive Psychology; J. B. Lippincott & Company: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1939. [Google Scholar]
- Mathews, A.; Mackintosh, B. A cognitive model of selective processing in anxiety. Cogn. Ther. Res. 1998, 22, 539–560. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Damasio, A. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness; Harcourt, Inc.: San Diego, CA, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, F. Mill on psychology and the moral sciences. In The Cambridge Companion to Mill; Skorupski, J.M., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Schmidgen, H. Wundt as chemist? A fresh look at his practice and theory of experimentation. Am. J. Psychol. 2003, 116, 469–476. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mandler, G. Origins of the cognitive (r)evolution. J. Hist. Behav. Sci. 2002, 38, 339–353. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barrouillet, P.; Bernardin, S.; Portrat, S.; Vergauwe, E.; Camos, V. Time and cognitive load in working memory. J. Exp. Psychol-Learn Mem. Cogn. 2007, 33, 570–585. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mill, J.S. August Comte and Positivism. 1865. Available online: http://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/16833/pg16833.txt (accessed on 20 December 2012).
- Plunkett, K.; Juola, P. A connectionist model of English past tense and plural morphology. Cogn. Sci. 1999, 23, 463–490. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benjamin, L.T. Structuralism and functionalism. In A History of Psychology; Benjamin, L.T., Ed.; Blackwell Publishing: Malden, MA, USA, 2009; pp. 123–127. [Google Scholar]
- Zhang, X.; Mathews, R.; Sun, R. Modeling meta-cognition in a cognitive architecture. Cogn. Syst. Res. 2006, 7, 327–338. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heyd, J. Mill and Comte on psychology. J. Hist. Behav. Sci. 1989, 25, 125–138. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Surprenant, A.M.; Neath, I. T.V. Moore’s (1939) Cognitive Psychology. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 1997, 4, 342–349. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Spelke, E.; Hirst, W.; Neisser, U. Skills of divided attention. Cognition 1976, 4, 215–230. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Houghton, G.; Tipper, S.P. A model of inhibitory mechanisms in selective attention. In Inhibitory Mechanisms in Attention, Memory and Language; Dagenbach, D., Carr, T., Eds.; Academic Press: San Diego, CA, USA, 1994; pp. 53–112. [Google Scholar]
- Neill, W.T.; Valdes, L.A.; Terry, K. M. Selective attention and the inhibitory control of cognition. In Interference and Inhibition in Cognition; Dempster, F.N., Brainerd, C.J., Eds.; Academic Press: New York, NY, USA, 1995; pp. 207–261. [Google Scholar]
- Beck, A.T. Depression: Causes and Treatment; University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Gwilliam, P.; Wells, A.; Cartwright-Hatton, S. Does meta–cognition or responsibility predict obsessive-compulsive symptoms: A test of the metacognitive model. Clin. Psychol. Psychother. 2004, 11, 137–144. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rosenthal, D.M. Consciousness, Content, and metacognitive judgment. Consc. Cogn. 2000, 9, 203–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nisbett, R.E.; Wilson, T.D. Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychol. Rev. 1977, 84, 231–259. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wells, A. Meta-Cognition and Worry: A Cognitive Model of Generalized Anxiety Disorder, Behav. Cogn. Psychother. 1995, 23, 301–320. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Reynolds, S.; Girling, E.; Coker, S.; Eastwood, L. The effect of mental health problems on children’s ability to discriminate amongst thoughts, feelings and behaviours. Cogn. Ther. Res. 2006, 30, 599–607. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eberth, J.; Sedlmeier, P. The effects of mindfulness meditation: A meta-Analysis. Mindfulness 2012, 3, 174–189. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ritschel, L.A.; Cheavens, J.S.; Nelson, J. Dialectical behavior therapy in an intensive outpatient program with a mixed-diagnostic sample. J. Clin. Psychol. 2012, 68, 221–235. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Robinson, D.N. Toward a Science of Human Nature; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Neisser, U. Cognitive Psychology; Appleton: New York, NY, USA, 1967. [Google Scholar]
© 2013 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/).
Share and Cite
Bistricky, S.L. Mill and Mental Phenomena: Critical Contributions to a Science of Cognition. Behav. Sci. 2013, 3, 217-231. https://doi.org/10.3390/bs3020217
Bistricky SL. Mill and Mental Phenomena: Critical Contributions to a Science of Cognition. Behavioral Sciences. 2013; 3(2):217-231. https://doi.org/10.3390/bs3020217
Chicago/Turabian StyleBistricky, Steven L. 2013. "Mill and Mental Phenomena: Critical Contributions to a Science of Cognition" Behavioral Sciences 3, no. 2: 217-231. https://doi.org/10.3390/bs3020217
APA StyleBistricky, S. L. (2013). Mill and Mental Phenomena: Critical Contributions to a Science of Cognition. Behavioral Sciences, 3(2), 217-231. https://doi.org/10.3390/bs3020217