“For If There Is No Resurrection of the Dead, Then Christ Has Not Been Raised Either”: Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Status of Christian Belief Statements
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Wittgensteinian Non-Cognitivism
2.1. Non-Cognitivism About Christian Belief Statements
Nothing would be more theoretical and unreal than to suppose that true Faith cannot exist except when moulded upon a Creed, and based upon Evidence; yet nothing would indicate a more shallow philosophy than to say that it ought carefully to be disjoined from dogmatic and argumentative statements.
He was buried, and he was raised from the dead on the third day, just as the Scriptures said. He was seen by Peter and then by the Twelve. After that, he was seen by more than 500 of his followers at one time, most of whom are still alive, though some have died. Then he was seen by James and later by all the apostles. Last of all, as though I had been born at the wrong time, I also saw him.(Holy Bible 2015, 1 Corinthians 15:4–8)
My account of what D.Z. Phillips has been claiming over many years in fidelity to Wittgenstein’s few explicit remarks on the subject, is that religion is a self-contained practice (of prayer, worship, public and private conduct, and the way we think about things), commitment to which involves no metaphysical or historical beliefs different from those of people who do not practise the religion. As an account of the Christian religion, as it has been practised by so many over two millennia, this seems manifestly false […] Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion suffers from a very one-sided diet of examples.
[Wittgenstein’s] remarks on religion do little more than assist us in identifying the interpretation of religious discourse favoured by Wittgenstein: they do not give us any substantial grounds for accepting that this interpretation adequately represents the content of religious statements as these are used by most people who think of themselves as religious believers.
The main problem with non-cognitive reinterpretation proposals is that they are not adequate in terms of religious phenomenology.(Löffler 2019, p. 124; my translation)5
Is it only a conceptual or logical confusion—as Wittgenstein seems to suggest—that a Christian can come to question his or her entire religious faith because he or she becomes convinced, on historical grounds, that the historical Jesus was utterly unlike the figure pictured in the four Gospels? Wittgenstein seems to argue in one place that it would make no difference to Christianity whether the Gospel narratives were true or false, that Christian faith is simply accepting a narrative (whether fictional or not) and orienting one’s life by it. Wittgenstein may think this but I do not believe it ‘does justice’ to the way in which historical and religious beliefs actually are related in Christian piety.(“I” in Phillips 2005b, p. 203)
[…] it seems extremely plausible that religious beliefs of this sort [for example, the belief in Christ’s resurrection or the belief in a Last Judgment day] do generally involve straightforwardly factual components. Whatever else the religious belief in a Judgement Day involves, it seems clear that it involves an empirical belief about the occurrence of a future event. If there will, in fact, never be any process of judgement in which a supernatural being holds people to account for what they have done, the religious belief is mistaken.
2.2. A Development in Later Wittgenstein
I believe: the word “believing” has wrought horrible havoc in religion. All the knotty thoughts about the ‘paradox’ of the eternal meaning of a historical fact and the like. But if instead of “belief in Christ” you would say: “love of Christ”, the paradox vanishes, that is, the irritation of the intellect. What does religion have to do with such a tickling of the intellect. (For someone or another this too may belong to their religion.)
It is not that now one could say: Yes, finally everything is simple—or intelligible. Nothing at all is intelligible, it is just not unintelligible.—(Wittgenstein 2023, pp. 106–107 = Ms-183,238–239)
There is, strange as it may sound, something that can be called religious knowledge, or understanding, and of which one can possess much without possessing much religion, which is, after all, a way of life. Some who, up to a certain degree, begin to become religious start with such an understanding: religious concepts and expressions begin to mean something to them.—But some others come to religion from another side. For example, they become more and more helpful, selfless, insightful, etc., and, eventually, the religious words also begin to mean something to them.(Wittgenstein 2011, Von Ludwig Wittgenstein an Arvid Sjögren, 9.10.1947; my translation)
2.3. Augustine’s Mistake
- Christian belief statements, or aspects of them, that cannot be described or translated into non-cognitive terms are superstition rather than genuine religious belief.
- Christian belief statements, or aspects of them, that cannot be described or translated into non-cognitive terms are parasitic on attitudes, thus preserving their cognitive content but exempting them from the cognitive truth-game.
- Christian belief statements, or aspects of them, that cannot be described or translated into non-cognitive terms are cognitive only so at the level of surface grammar, not depth grammar.
3. Three Possible Objections to Cognitivism
3.1. “The Cognitive Aspect of Christian Belief Statements Is Superstition Only”
Is any religion true? Is it not based on imagination or sentiment or feeling? Christianity, most emphatically, at least, asserts the contrary. It holds that its truths are reached by the very same intelligence that is operative in science and with the same certainty. These truths are that God exists, that He created the world, that He created man with an immortal soul and a free will, and finally, that God came into this world as man. Is this last fact true? Christianity appeals to the historical records contained in the New Testament, and asserts that these records are trustworthy, that the events there narrated did happen, even when judged by the severest scientific criticism.
For a Catholic surely it is an essential part of the mass to believe that the rite was instituted by Christ on Maundy Thursday. And here it seems to me you have ‘opinion’ and ‘hypothesis’, and the possibility of error.
[…] if language-games and forms of life are insular, inscrutable, self-regulating, and self-providing for norms of meaning and if, consequently, Wittgensteinian religion is thuswise disconnected from other ingredients of human life, then Wittgenstein must be wrong in his depiction of the religious arena.
Thus belief in God would now generally be called ‘faith’—belief in God at all, not belief that God will help one, for example. This is a great pity. It has had a disgusting effect on thought about religion. The astounding idea that there should be such a thing as believing God has been lost sight of.
3.2. “The Cognitive Aspect of Christian Belief Statements Is Parasitic on Religious Attitude Only”
If religious beliefs are supposed to be true in the same sense as other beliefs, they cannot be judged by a distinctive set of standards that are internal to the religious world-picture to which they belong; they are answerable to the same standards of truth and rationality that we apply elsewhere. On the other hand, if religion is a self-contained practice, with no implications for our other beliefs—if, in particular, religious utterances and beliefs are not supposed to be literally true—then religion is not answerable to the standards of truth and rationality that are appropriate to non-religious beliefs.
On miracles, Newman cites the case of Christians, who taken by savages had their tongues cut out, and yet they could speak. He gives a natural explanation for this—if the tongue is only half cut off a man cannot speak, but if wholly cut off a man still can—but Newman then goes on to say that it may nevertheless have been a miracle.(Wittgenstein 1986, p. 34; 22 August 1949)
3.3. “The Cognitive Aspect of Christian Belief Statements Is Cognitive in Surface Grammar Only”
D: Why not? Wittgensteinians always claim to tell us what we really mean. Why not ask Christians what they do mean? If the majority says they mean such-and-such, that settles the matter. You can do this kind of philosophy by Gallup poll. C: No you can’t, because when reference is made to what people mean, the reference is to the role the words play in their lives, not to the account they would give if asked. Notoriously, in giving that account our own words can lead us astray.
C: As Peter Winch has said, we can give a date for the resurrection, but what happened on that date, the resurrection itself, cannot be determined historically, any more than that the person crucified was the Son of God. I: But this is the trouble. Speaking in the way C just has, simply does not accord with what Christians believe. C: But what do Christians believe? You can’t find that out by asking them, since their answers will themselves be a form of philosophical or theological reflection. I: I’m not suggesting that we do ask people, but I am saying that we need to examine the doctrine.
Besides other points in common we both [the Anglican and the Catholic] hold, that certain doctrines are necessary to be believed for salvation; we both believe in the doctrines of the Trinity, Incarnation, and Atonement; in original sin; in the necessity of regeneration; in the supernatural grace of the Sacraments; in the apostolical succession; in the obligation of faith and obedience, and in the eternity of future punishment.
But I would ridicule it, not by saying it is based on insufficient evidence. I would say: here is a man who is cheating himself. You can say: this man is ridiculous because he believes, and bases it on weak reasons.
4. Can Depth Grammar Be Mistaken? A Cognitive Wittgensteinian Answer
For if there is no resurrection of the dead, then Christ has not been raised either. And if Christ has not been raised, then all our preaching is useless, and your faith is useless. And we apostles would all be lying about God—for we have said that God raised Christ from the grave. But that can’t be true if there is no resurrection of the dead. And if there is no resurrection of the dead, then Christ has not been raised. And if Christ has not been raised, then your faith is useless and you are still guilty of your sins. In that case, all who have died believing in Christ are lost! And if our hope in Christ is only for this life, we are more to be pitied than anyone in the world.(Holy Bible 2015, 1 Corinthians 15:13–19)
For when we consider the subject attentively, how few things there are which we can ascertain for ourselves by our own senses and reason! After all, what do we know without trusting others? We know that we are in a certain state of health, in a certain place, have been alive for a certain number of years, have certain principles and likings, have certain persons around us, and perhaps have in our lives travelled to certain places at a distance. But what do we know more? Are there not towns (we will say) within fifty or sixty miles of us which we have never seen, and which, nevertheless, we fully believe to be as we have heard them described? To extend our view;—we know that land stretches in every direction of us, a certain number of miles, and then there is sea on all sides; that we are in an island. But who has seen the land all around, and has proved for himself that the fact is so? What, then, convinces us of it? the report of others,—this trust, this faith in testimony which, when religion is concerned, then, and only then, the proud and sinful would fain call irrational.
5. Postscript
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For all works published from the Wittgenstein Nachlass, except for the Philosophical Investigations—both its earlier so-called “Part I” (Wittgenstein (2009a)) and “Part II” (Wittgenstein (2009b))—the Nachlass sources are also given by using “Ms-” (for manuscript) or “Ts-“ (for typescript) followed by G. H. von Wright’s catalogue number (see von Wright 1982) and page number. The Nachlass sources can be viewed in their original context in the form of both transcriptions and facsimiles on Wittgenstein (2015a) or Wittgenstein (2016). For example, the Nachlass source of the remark cited from Wittgenstein (1998), pp. 37e–38e is Ms-120,42r-42v of which a facsimile can be viewed at http://wittgensteinsource.org/BFE/Ms-120,42r_f (accessed on 20 February 2025) and http://wittgensteinsource.org/BFE/Ms-120,42v_f (accessed on 20 February 2025), a linear transcription at http://wittgensteinsource.org/BTE/Ms-120,42r[2]et42v[1]et43r[1]_n (accessed on 20 February 2025) and a diplomatic transcription at http://wittgensteinsource.org/BTE/Ms-120,42r[2]et42v[1]et43r[1]_d (accessed on 20 February 2025). |
2 | The controversy between non-cognitivists and cognitivists regarding Christian belief is old. One example is the “Fragmentenstreit” with G.E. Lessing as one of the participants. With the remark cited from Wittgenstein (1998, pp. 37e–38e) Wittgenstein might have referred to Lessing (1839); also see Wittgenstein’s reference to Lessing in Wittgenstein (2023), p. 72 = Ms-183,148–149 (Pichler 2024, p. 253). Another example, from the early 20th century, is Scholz (1921) who critically discusses Hans Vaihinger’s idea of religion ‘as if.’ Contributions from the last fifty years are legion; the literature referred to in this article provides only a glimpse. |
3 | The editors of Wittgenstein’s so-called Whewell’s Court lectures of 1938–1941 (Wittgenstein 2017), Volker Munz and Bernhard Ritter, argue that what Cyril Barrett, on the basis of Yorick Smythies’ notes, had edited as the third lecture “on religious belief” (Wittgenstein 1966, pp. 65–72) is identical with lecture 16 of the “Lectures on Similarity” (Wittgenstein 2017, pp. 126–132), and date it, with the help of Norman Malcolm’s notebook, to 11 December 1939. Furthermore, they think that this lecture “has nothing to do with a supposed set of lectures on religious belief, whose putative unity may be nothing more than the product of an undeclared editorial intervention” (Wittgenstein 2017, p. 86). |
4 | See Nielsen (1967) who attributed “Wittgensteinian fideism” to “Winch, Hughes, Malcolm, Geach, Cavell, Cameron and Coburn” (p. 191). Other early critics of Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion include Hepburn (1963) and Hick (1964). See, e.g., Hick (1964, p. 241): “I do not know how it could ever be demonstratively proved that Amos and Paul and the other biblical writers presupposed the real existence of the God whom they worshipped; but I also think that anyone who doubts that this presupposition operated in their minds must be blinded in a very sophisticated way to the natural and ordinary meanings of words. But if such first-order religious utterances as ‘God showed his love for us …’ do presuppose and imply that God exists, then religious belief cannot after all be immune from the familiar questions concerning grounds, meaning and mode of verification”. An early response came from Phillips (1970), who became, in the eyes of critics, the main Wittgensteinian “fideist”. Dalferth (2005, pp. 291–94) categorizes Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion under three main labels: fideism, unhistorical analysis, and non-realism. Kerr (2005, p. 260) references Hans W. Frei’s Types of Christian Theology (1992) for a description of fideists: “Christian theology, for these people, ‘is strictly the grammar of the faith, a procedure in self-description for which there is no external correlative’. Moreover, theology of this type ‘is also a technical articulation of a religious outlook or sensibility that has a strong appeal to Christian evangelicals, for whom the language of the Bible is not so much factually correct as—much more importantly—inspired in its nurturing effect on the believer’s heart’”. For a thorough discussion of the label “fideism” as well as other critiques of Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion, see Carroll (2014, chs. 4–5). Schönbaumsfeld (2024) argues that the “fideism” label is inappropriate for Wittgenstein. |
5 | For an overview and systematic discussion of criticisms of Wittgensteinian non-cognitivism, see Carroll (2014, ch. 3.3). Of course, as this article shows, criticism of non-cognitivism about religious belief statements has also been voiced from within Wittgensteinian philosophy; examples include Hyman (2001), Richter (2001), Schroeder (2007), Biletzki (2010), Child (2011, pp. 223–29), Citron (2012), Bremer (2013), Pichler (2024) and Pichler and Sunday Grève (2024). |
6 | Among others, Richter (2001), Schroeder (2007), Carroll (2014, pp. 67, 68) and Pichler (2024, pp. 280–85) all represent variants of the distinction between “Wittgenstein the philosopher” and “Wittgenstein the man” when dealing with Wittgenstein’s views on religious belief. |
7 | Other approaches to Wittgenstein’s remarks about religious belief and religion include the view that “Wittgenstein saw religions as essentially grammars of wonder” (Cahill 2021, pp. 168, 172; also see Koritensky 2002, pp. 32–44 et passim; and Perissinotto 2024, pp. 210–11). A second view, strongly suggested by Wittgenstein himself in the Lectures on Religious Belief, is that of religious belief as a picture and religious conversion as an aspect-shift (for a discussion see von Sass 2010, pp. 208–14, 348–62). A third view is offered by Citron (2012) who treats Wittgenstein’s discussion of religious belief statements not as, correct or incorrect, description of religious belief grammar (as this article and most of the work critical or supportive of Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion do), or as an expression of Wittgenstein’s personal preferences in religious belief (as, for example, Richter 2001; and Schroeder 2007, do), but as a methodology for offering objects of comparison that, “each with a different grammar” (Citron 2012, p. 26), reveal the “logically mixed, indeterminate, and fluid” (Citron 2012, p. 18) grammar of religious belief language and language in general. Citron ascribes this approach less to a development than to a continuous “alternative strand” in the later Wittgenstein, from 1933 at the latest. Yet another approach is that religious belief statements express undisputed hinge commitments or propositions whose truth “belongs to our frame of reference” (Wittgenstein 1969, §83 = Ms-174,17v); for examples see Schönbaumsfeld (2001), Schönbaumsfeld (2024) and Pritchard (2024). Bremer (2013) highlights a weak point of religious hinge epistemology when he states: “[…] it seems to be demonstrable that religious belief statements are essentially different from other worldview-constitutive propositions. The other worldview-constitutive propositions and convictions can appear to be undoubtedly certain (or can only become doubtful if they lose their regulative status). In contrast to this, doubt about religious propositions with conviction is not only never excluded, but—as we have seen—is also possible when the religious convictions remain in force at the regulative level. For this reason, it is a mistake to want to eliminate the possibility of doubt in religious beliefs. For with religious elements of worldviews, doubt not only becomes possible, but can already be formulated within the realm of religious belief” (p. 152; my translation). |
8 | For Wittgenstein’s own use of the term “form of life” (“Lebensform”), see, for example, Wittgenstein (1966, p. 58); Wittgenstein (2009a, §§ 19, 23, 241); Wittgenstein (2009b, §i-1, xi-345); Wittgenstein (1969, §358 = Ms-175,55v); Wittgenstein (1992, p. 95e = Ms-176,51v). |
9 | |
10 | One anonymous reviewer of this paper has drawn attention to the fact that in Christian theology, at least in its Catholic tradition, the use of reason, such as in natural theology, serves as a “preamble” to faith, which is belief based on God’s authority. The reviewer emphasizes that while it may seem that belief based on authority is noncognitive—more akin to obedience to a command rather than, in the words of Pichler and Sunday Grève (2024), based on the truth-game—this is not how Catholic theologians have historically viewed faith. Instead, they considered faith to be belief grounded not merely on any authority, but on the authority of truth itself. Thomas Aquinas speaks of the object of faith being “the First Truth” (Summa Theologica (Aquinas 1981): II-II, Q.1, Art.1). |
11 | Other authors criticizing non-cognitivism for compartmentalization include Addis (2001, pp. 92–95), Child (2011, pp. 227–29) and Citron (2012, pp. 19–20). |
12 | For studies of the concept of miracle and its role in Wittgenstein’s philosophy see, for example, Koritensky (2002, esp., pp. 278–86) and Perissinotto (2024). Perissinotto notes that Wittgenstein’s “talk of ‘nonsensicality’ as the ‘very essence’ of an expression will later be considered by Wittgenstein to be wrong and misleading” (p. 209). He also sees a close connection between “the way in which Wittgenstein understands miracles and the miraculous” and “the way in which he understands and practises philosophy” (p. 210). Unfortunately, it is not possible in this article to discuss Wittgenstein’s distinction between sense and nonsense and the debates surrounding it in more detail and to relate them to the theme. For recent discussions see Mulhall (2024) (focusing on the relationship between Wittgenstein’s view of nonsense and his treatment of ineffability), Wang-Kathrein (forthcoming; focusing on the relationship between Wittgenstein’s understanding of nonsense and his “Nonsense Collection”, which includes extracts on and from Christian religion) and Appelqvist (forthcoming; focusing on the role of nonsense in the tradition of Christian belief). |
13 | As someone who highly valued poetry (see Wittgenstein 1998, p. 28e), Wittgenstein might have appreciated Jean Paul’s “Rede des toten Christus vom Weltgebäude herab, daß kein Gott sei” (1796–1797), which gives powerful poetic expression to the imagined discovery that there is no God (see Jean Paul 1987). |
14 | The phrase of “confused practice” is borrowed from Mounce (1973) which makes a distinction between a language game (a set of concepts) and a practice; according to Mounce, only the latter, the practice, can be confused. For the discussion here, this restriction does not play a role, and if a practice is confused, also the language game(s) and the depth grammar(s) connected with it can be treated as confused. To Phillips (2005a, pp. 174–78), superstition is a prime example of a confused practice which can be linked to the “magical view of signs”: “I found help in Rhees’ penetrating observation that a magical view of signs can lead, not only to metaphysics (a confused gloss on a practice), but also to superstitions (confused practices)” (Phillips 2005b, p. 198). |
15 | For the interpretation of Wittgenstein (2009a, §241), see also Baker and Hacker (2009, p. 235): “The interlocutor misunderstands the claim that agreement is part of the scaffolding out of which our language operates (§240), taking it to mean that it is general agreement that decides what is true and what is false. His question expresses the suspicion that W. has abolished the objectivity of truth. But this is mistaken. It is what we say, the propositions that we propound in making judgements, in expressing our thoughts, that are true or false. Whether they are true or false is determined by reality, not by whether human beings agree in accepting or rejecting them”. |
References
- Addis, Mark. 2001. D. Z. Phillips’ Fideism in Wittgenstein’s Mirror. In Wittgenstein and Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Robert L. Arrington and Mark Addis. London: Routledge, pp. 85–100. [Google Scholar]
- Anscombe, G. Elizabeth M. 2008. Faith in a Hard Ground: Essays on Religion, Philosophy and Ethics. Edited by Mary Geach and Luke Gormally. Exeter: Imprint Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Appelqvist, Hanne. Forthcoming. Wittgenstein on the Ineffability of God.
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1981. Summa Theologica. Complete English Edition in Five Volumes: Volume III. Secunda Secundae, QQ 1–148. Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Allen: Christian Classics. [Google Scholar]
- Augustinus, Aurelius. 1888. Die Bekenntnisse des Heiligen Augustinus. Translated by Otto Lachmann. Leipzig: Reclam. [Google Scholar]
- Bailey, Alan. 2001. Wittgenstein and the Interpretation of Religious Discourse. In Wittgenstein and Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Robert L. Arrington and Mark Addis. London: Routledge, pp. 119–36. [Google Scholar]
- Baker, Gordon P., and Peter M. S. Hacker. 2009. Volume 2 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations: Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity. Essays and Exegesis of §§185–242, 2nd ed. Edited by Peter M. S. Hacker. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Biletzki, Anat. 2010. The ‘Language and World’ of Religion. In Language and World. Part Two: Signs, Minds and Actions. Edited by Volker Munz, Klaus Puhl and Joseph Wang. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag, pp. 147–56. [Google Scholar]
- Biletzki, Anat. 2024. What Is a ‘Democratic’ Form of Life? In Wittgenstein and Democratic Politics: Language, Dialogue and Political Forms of Life. Edited by Lotar Rasiński, Anat Biletzki, Leszek Koczanowicz, Alois Pichler and Thomas Wallgren. London: Routledge, pp. 144–61. [Google Scholar]
- Bremer, Józef. 2013. Sprachspiel und Religion: Ludwig Wittgensteins Auffassung des religiösen Glaubens. In Spiel: Facetten Seiner Ideengeschichte. Edited by Michel Henri Kowalewicz in Verbindung mit Gunter Scholtz and Karl Acham. Münster: Mentis, pp. 147–60. [Google Scholar]
- Brusotti, Marco. 2024. ’Ich glaube: es ist durch das Wort ‚glauben‘ in der Religion furchtbar viel Unheil angerichtet worden.‘ Wittgenstein und das Ende des Totemismus. In Religionsphilosophie nach Wittgenstein—Sprachen und Gewissheiten des Glaubens. Edited by Esther Heinrich-Ramharter. Berlin: J. B. Metzler, pp. 93–125. [Google Scholar]
- Cahill, Kevin. 2021. Towards a Philosophical Anthropology of Culture: Naturalism, Relativism and Skepticism. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, Thomas D. 2014. Wittgenstein Within the Philosophy of Religion. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Child, William. 2011. Wittgenstein. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Citron, Gabriel. 2012. Simple Objects of Comparison for Complex Grammars: An Alternative Strand in Wittgenstein’s Later Remarks on Religion. Philosophical Investigations 35: 18–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dalferth, Ingolf U. 2005. Wittgenstein: The Theological Reception. In Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Mario von der Ruhr. London: Routledge, pp. 273–301. [Google Scholar]
- Drury, Maurice O’Connor. 2017. The Selected Writings of Maurice O’Connor Drury: On Wittgenstein, Philosophy, Religion and Psychiatry. Edited by John Hayes. London: Bloomsbury Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Engelmann, Mauro L. 2024. Answering Sraffa on Religion: Wittgenstein Walking the Tightrope. JOLMA 5: 65–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frege, Gottlob. 1964. The Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Translated and Edited by Montgomery Furth. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Harvey, Van A. 2005. Contemplative Philosophy and Doing Justice to Religion. In Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Mario von der Ruhr. London: Routledge, pp. 187–96. [Google Scholar]
- Hepburn, Ronald W. 1963. From World to God. Mind 72: 40–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hick, John. 1964. Sceptics and Believers. In Faith and the Philosophers. Edited by John Hick. New York: Macmillan, pp. 235–50. [Google Scholar]
- Holy Bible. 2015. New Living Translation. Carol Stream: Tyndale House Foundation. [Google Scholar]
- Hyman, John. 2001. The Gospel According to Wittgenstein. In Wittgenstein and Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Robert L. Arrington and Mark Addis. London: Routledge, pp. 1–11. [Google Scholar]
- Jäger, Christoph. 2003. Wittgenstein über Gewißheit und religiösen Glauben. In Die Sprachen der Religion. Edited by Florian Uhl and Artur Boelderl. Berlin: Parerga, pp. 221–56. [Google Scholar]
- Kerr, Fergus. 2005. The Reception of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy by Theologians. In Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Mario von der Ruhr. London: Routledge, pp. 253–72. [Google Scholar]
- Kfouri, André. 2023. Further Affinities between Wittgenstein and Newman. In 100 Years of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus—70 Years after Wittgenstein’s Death: A Critical Assessment. Contributions of the Austrian Ludw Wittgenstein Society XXIX. Edited by Alois Pichler, Esther Heinrich-Ramharter and Friedrich Stadler, in cooperation with Joseph Wang-Kathrein. Kirchberg/W: ALWS, pp. 390–97. [Google Scholar]
- Kienzler, Wolfgang. 2006. Wittgenstein and John Henry Newman on certainty. Grazer Philosophische Studien 71: 117–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Koritensky, Andreas. 2002. Wittgensteins Phänomenologie der Religion. München: Kohlhammer. [Google Scholar]
- Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim. 1839. Über den Beweis des Geistes und der Kraft. In Sämtliche Schriften. Edited by Karl Lachmann. Berlin: Voß‘sche Buchhandlung, pp. 33–39. vol. 10. [Google Scholar]
- Löffler, Winfried. 2019. Einführung in die Religionsphilosophie. Darmstadt: WBG. [Google Scholar]
- Moore, Gareth. 2005. Wittgenstein’s English Parson: Some Reflections on the Reception of Wittgenstein in the Philosophy of Religion. In Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Mario von der Ruhr. London: Routledge, pp. 209–28. [Google Scholar]
- Mounce, Howard O. 1973. Understanding a Primitive Society. Philosophy 48: 347–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mulhall, Stephen. 2001. Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Religion. In Philosophy of Religion in the 21st Century. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Timothy Tessin. Basingstoke: Palgrave, pp. 95–118. [Google Scholar]
- Mulhall, Stephen. 2024. Ineffability. Or, the Uses of Nonsense According to Wittgenstein. In Religionsphilosophie nach Wittgenstein—Sprachen und Gewissheiten des Glaubens. Edited by Esther Heinrich-Ramharter. Berlin: J. B. Metzler, pp. 227–44. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1859. On Consulting the Faithful in Matters of Doctrine. London: Burns and Oates. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1903. An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent. London: Longmans. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1907a. Parochial and Plain Sermons, Volume 1. London: Longmans. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1907b. The Idea of a University. London: Longmans. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1908. Sermons Preached on Various Occasions. London: Longmans. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1909. Fifteen Sermons Preached Before the University of Oxford Between A.D. 1826 and 1843. London: Longmans. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1913. Apologia Pro Vita Sua. London: Longmans. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 1914. Sermon Notes of John Henry Cardinal Newman 1849–1878. London: Longmans. [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen, Kai. 1967. Wittgensteinian Fideism. Philosophy 42: 191–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- O’Hara, Charles Willibrord. 1931. Science and Religion. In Science & Religion: A Symposium. Edited by Julian Huxley, J. Arthur Thomson and J. S. Haldane. London: Heinemann, pp. 107–16. [Google Scholar]
- Paul, Jean. 1987. Siebenkäs: Blumen-, Frucht- und Dornenstücke oder Ehestand, Tod und Hochzeit des Armenadvokaten F. St. Siebenkäs im Reichsmarktflecken Kuhschnappel. Frankfurt am Main: Insel. [Google Scholar]
- Perissinotto, Luigi. 2024. Wittgenstein on miracles. Rosmini Studies 11: 197–216. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Phillips, Dewi Z. 1970. Religious Beliefs and Language-Games. Ratio 12: 24–46. [Google Scholar]
- Phillips, Dewi Z. 2001. Voices in Discussion. In Philosophy of Religion in the 21st Century. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Timothy Tessin. Basingstoke: Palgrave, pp. 144–50. [Google Scholar]
- Phillips, Dewi Z. 2005a. Just Say the Word: Magical and Logical Conceptions. In Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Mario von der Ruhr. London: Routledge, pp. 171–86. [Google Scholar]
- Phillips, Dewi Z. 2005b. Voices in Discussion. In Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Mario von der Ruhr. London: Routledge, pp. 197–208. [Google Scholar]
- Pichler, Alois. 2023. Style, Method and Philosophy in Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pichler, Alois. 2024. Glaube und Aberglaube nach Wittgenstein: Zu nonkognitiven Deutungen der Grammatik des religiösen Glaubens. In Religionsphilosophie nach Wittgenstein—Sprachen und Gewissheiten des Glaubens. Edited by Esther Heinrich-Ramharter. Berlin: J. B. Metzler, pp. 245–86. [Google Scholar]
- Pichler, Alois, and Sebastian Sunday Grève. 2024. Cognitivism about Religious Belief in Later Wittgenstein. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 97: 61–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pritchard, Duncan. 2024. Religious Vertigo. In Religionsphilosophie nach Wittgenstein—Sprachen und Gewissheiten des Glaubens. Edited by Esther Heinrich-Ramharter. Berlin: J. B. Metzler, pp. 287–305. [Google Scholar]
- Richter, Duncan. 2001. Missing the Entire Point: Wittgenstein and Religion. Religious Studies 37: 161–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scholz, Heinrich. 1921. Die Religionsphilosophie des Als-Ob: Eine Nachprüfung Kants und des Idealistischen Positivismus. Leipzig: F. Meiner. [Google Scholar]
- Schönbaumsfeld, Genia. 2001. Wittgenstein über religiösen Glauben. In Der Denker als Seiltänzer. Edited by Ulrich Arnswald and Anja Weiberg. Berlin: Parerga, pp. 179–92. [Google Scholar]
- Schönbaumsfeld, Genia. 2023. Wittgenstein on Religious Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schönbaumsfeld, Genia. 2024. ‘Making it a Question of Science‘—Wittgensteins Kritik an Father O’Hara und dem Szientismus in der Religion Wittgenstein über religiösen Glauben. In Religionsphilosophie nach Wittgenstein—Sprachen und Gewissheiten des Glaubens. Edited by Esther Heinrich-Ramharter. Berlin: J. B. Metzler, pp. 73–92. [Google Scholar]
- Schroeder, Severin. 2007. The tightrope walker. Ratio 20: 442–463. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2001. Philosophical Theism. In Philosophy of Religion in the 21st Century. Edited by Dewi Z. Phillips and Timothy Tessin. Basingstoke: Palgrave, pp. 3–20. [Google Scholar]
- Trigg, Roger. 1997. Theological Realism and Antirealism. In A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Philip L. Quinn and Charles Taliaferro. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 213–20. [Google Scholar]
- Trigg, Roger. 2014. Religious Diversity: Philosophical and Political Dimensions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Venturinha, Nuno. 2019. Wittgenstein’s Religious Epistemology and Interfaith Dialogue. In Interpreting Interreligious Relations with Wittgenstein. Edited by Gorazd Andrejč and Daniel Weiss. Leiden: Brill, pp. 97–113. [Google Scholar]
- von Sass, Hartmut. 2010. Sprachspiele des Glaubens: Eine Studie zur kontemplativen Religionsphilosophie von D.Z. Phillips mit Ständiger Rücksicht auf Ludwig Wittgenstein. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- von Wright, Georg Henrik. 1982. The Wittgenstein papers. In Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 35–62. [Google Scholar]
- Wang-Kathrein, Joseph. Forthcoming. Nonsensical Actions and the Justification of Rules. In 100 Years of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus–70 Years After Wittgenstein’s Death. Edited by Esther Heinrich-Ramharter, Alois Pichler and Friedrich Stadler. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter.
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by Charles K. Ogden. London: Kegan Paul. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1966. Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief. Edited by Cyril Barrett. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1969. On Certainty. Edited by G. Elizabeth M. Anscombe and Georg Henrik von Wright. Translated by Denis Paul, and G. Elizabeth M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1992. Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume 2. Edited by Georg Henrik von Wright and Heikki Nyman. Translated by C. Grant Luckhardt, and Maximilian A. E. Aue. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1993a. A Lecture on Ethics. Edited by Rush Rhees. In Philosophical Occasions: 1912–1951. Edited by James C. Klagge and Alfred Nordmann. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett, pp. 36–44. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1993b. Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough. Edited by Rush Rhees, translated by A. C. Miles and Rush Rhees. In Philosophical Occasions: 1912–1951. Edited by James C. Klagge and Alfred Nordmann. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett, pp. 115–55. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1998. Culture and Value: A Selection from the Posthumous Remains. Edited by Georg Henrik von Wright in collaboration with Heikki Nyman, revised edition of the text by Alois Pichler. Translated by Peter Winch. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2003. Public and Private Occasions. Edited by James C. Klagge and Alfred Nordmann. Lanham, Boulder, New York and Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009a. Philosophical Investigations, 4th rev. ed. Edited by Peter M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte. Translated by G. Elizabeth M. Anscombe, Peter M. S. Hacker, and Joachim Schulte. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009b. Philosophy of Psychology—A Fragment. In Philosophical Investigations, 4th rev. ed. Edited by Peter M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte. Translated by G. Elizabeth M. Anscombe, Peter M. S. Hacker, and Joachim Schulte. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2011. Wittgenstein: Gesamtbriefwechsel/Complete Correspondence (Innsbrucker Electronic Edition), 2nd release. Edited by Anna Coda, Gabriel Citron, Barbara Halder, Allan Janik, Ulrich Lobis, Kerstin Mayr, Brian McGuinness, Michael Schorner, Monika Seekircher and Joseph Wang. Charlottesville: Intelex. Available online: http://www.nlx.com/collections/166 (accessed on 20 February 2025).
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2015a. Wittgenstein Source Bergen Nachlass Edition. Edited by the Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen under the direction of Alois Pichler, in Wittgenstein Source. Bergen: The Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen. Available online: http://www.wittgensteinsource.org (accessed on 20 February 2025).
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2015b. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Conversations with Rush Rhees (1939–1950): From the Notes of Rush Rhees, edited by Gabriel Citron. Mind 124: 1–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2016. Interactive Dynamic Presentation (IDP) of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Nachlass. Edited by the Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen under the direction of Alois Pichler. Bergen: The Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen. Available online: https://wab.uib.no/transform/wab.php?modus=opsjoner (accessed on 20 February 2025).
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2017. Wittgenstein’s Whewell’s Court Lectures: Cambridge 1938–1941: From the Notes by Yorick Smythies. Edited by Volker A. Munz and Bernhard Ritter. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2023. Movements of Thought. Edited by James C. Klagge and Alfred Nordmann. Translated by Alfred Nordmann. Lanham, Boulder, New York and Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig, and Maurice O’C. Drury. 1984a. Conversations with Wittgenstein. In Recollections of Wittgenstein. Edited by Rush Rhees. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 97–171. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig, and Norman Malcolm. 1984b. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. Second edition with Wittgenstein’s letters to Malcolm, with a biographical sketch by Georg Henrik von Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig, and Oets Kolk Bouwsma. 1986. Wittgenstein: Conversations 1949–1951. Edited by Jimmy L. Craft and Ronald E. Hustwit. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Pichler, A. “For If There Is No Resurrection of the Dead, Then Christ Has Not Been Raised Either”: Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Status of Christian Belief Statements. Religions 2025, 16, 306. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030306
Pichler A. “For If There Is No Resurrection of the Dead, Then Christ Has Not Been Raised Either”: Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Status of Christian Belief Statements. Religions. 2025; 16(3):306. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030306
Chicago/Turabian StylePichler, Alois. 2025. "“For If There Is No Resurrection of the Dead, Then Christ Has Not Been Raised Either”: Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Status of Christian Belief Statements" Religions 16, no. 3: 306. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030306
APA StylePichler, A. (2025). “For If There Is No Resurrection of the Dead, Then Christ Has Not Been Raised Either”: Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Status of Christian Belief Statements. Religions, 16(3), 306. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030306