Saadya on Necessary Knowledge
Abstract
:1. The Epistemological Background: Necessary Knowledge in Kalām
Knowledge is the notion that entails a sense of certainty [in] the soul (al-ma‘nā alladhī yaqtaḍī sukūn al-nafs) of the knower at what he has obtained.
And now that we have finished expounding, as much as we felt it desirable, the matter of resolving uncertainties and doubts, it behooves us to explain what is meant by conviction (i‘tiqād). We say that it is a notion that arises in the soul in regard to the actual state of anything that is known. When the cream of speculation emerges, when it is embraced and enfolded by the intellects and, through them acquired and digested by the souls, then the person becomes convinced of the truth of the notion he has thus acquired. He then deposits it in his soul for a future occasion or for future occasions, in accordance with the statement of Scripture: “Wise men lay up knowledge” [Prov. 10:14].
[In order to establish knowledge of tradition:] therefore did He render the human mind susceptible to the acceptance of authenticated tradition and the human soul capable of finding repose (li-‘l-sukūn) therein, so that His Scriptures and traditions might be acknowledged as true.(Saadya, L, 126; K, 130; R, 155–156)
The words gladden the heart (Ps. 19:8) convey that the heart is at rest (yaskun ilayhi al-qalb) on account of the truth of premises and conclusions. The words enlightening the eyes (ibid.) allude to the light emanating from the word (kalām) and the removal of ambiguity therefrom.
There are only two types of knowledge: One occurs by virtue of us in the ways mentioned above (speculation and inference), and is accordingly called acquired knowledge (‘ilm muktasab). By nature, it can be denied by its knower from his soul with uncertainty… The other is created by God in us, and accordingly called necessary knowledge (‘ilm ḍarūrī). Its definition is that which is impossible to be denied by its knower with uncertainty.
There are two kinds of knowledge [belonging to human beings and other animals]: the necessary and the acquired. Their difference lies in the fact that for the acquired knowledge, the knower has power (qudra) to know and infer it; for the necessary knowledge, neither his inference nor his power is involved in its occurrence.(Al-Baghdādī 1928, p. 8)
The claim of one who says that the world does not exist is unacceptable because of the self-imposing (iḍtirār) realization of the existence of the world and also because of the self-imposing (iḍtirār) realization of our own existence.
All this (knowledge of the affliction of one’s own body or removing of this affliction) is naturally understood by everyone; people know it intuitively (iḍtirār) and are not troubled by any doubts about it.
2. Saadya’s Necessary Knowledge
We declare that there are three [such] bases. The first is the knowledge of observation; the second, the knowledge of the intellect, and the third, the knowledge that necessity compels to (ma dafa‘at al-darūra illayhi)… As for ourselves, the community of monotheists, we accept these three bases of knowledge to be true. To them, however, we add a fourth base, which we have derived by means of the [other] three, and which has thus become for us a further principle. That is the validity of authentic tradition.(L, 12–14; K, 14–15; R, 16–18)
Knowledge of necessities (‘ilm al-ḍarūriyāt) is that which, if not accepted as true, would compel his denial of a sensible or intelligible. Since, however, he cannot very well negate either of these two, the fact forces him (al-’amr yaḍṭirruhu) to regard the notion as being correct. Thus, we are forced (nuḍṭarr) to affirm, although we have never seen it, that man possesses a soul, in order not to deny its manifest activity. [We are] also [ forced to affirm], although we have never seen it, that every soul is endowed with intellect, in order not to deny the latter’s manifest activity.(L, 13; K, 14; R, 16–17)
Besides that it confirms for us the validity of necessary knowledge (al-‘ilm al-ḍarūrī), [that is to say] that whatever leads to the rejection of the sensible or intelligible is false.(L, 15; K, 16; R, 19)
As for the knowledges of necessities (al-ḍarūriyāt min al-‘ulūm), when our senses perceive and verify something, and when the conviction of that thing can be held in our souls only by virtue of the simultaneous conviction of other things, we must be convinced of all these things, be they few or many in number, since the sense percept in question arises only by means of them (yaqūm… illā bihā).(L, 16; K, 18; R, 21)
If, again, we assumed that these attributes appertained to them (spiritual atoms) after they had attained the composite status, then that part of these beings which is with us would necessarily (bi-’l-ḍarūra) be within our reach.(L, 45; K, 48; R, 54)
But suppose we note that the [pretended] prophet pays no attention to us but makes us witness the miracles and marvels so that we see them perforce (ḍarūra). What shall we say to him in that case?(L, 133; K, 136; R, 164)
The wisdom (for intellect to infer the Creator’s attributes from His creatures) needs time to acquire (iktisāb) [Kafih/Goodman: for it does not develop automatically (bi-ḍarūra) in a person but must be acquired]. Then it says that the wisdom in this state is as valid as knowledge of senses and necessity (‘ilm al-ḥawās wa-’l-ḍarūrāt), deducing for us that the Creator his wisdom with him.
By rejecting the first source (perception), they have automatically rejected the second (intellection) and the third (“necessary knowledge”), since the latter two are based upon the first.(L, 13; K, 14; R, 17)12
That which occurs in us through a means is the knowledge of the perceptible things, and perception is the means to it. That which occurs through what resembles a means is like the knowledge of the state (hāl) together with the knowledge of the essence (dhāt), and the knowledge of the essence is a root (aṣl) of the knowledge of the state and resembles a means to the knowledge of the latter. The difference between what occurs in us through a means and what resembles a means is that, it is possible for the former to persist without a means; yet, this is not the case in the latter. Therefore, God may create in us a knowledge of perceptible things without perception, but may not create a knowledge of the state without a knowledge of the essence; for the knowledge of essence is a root for that of the state, and resembles a means to the latter.
In perception, we know that the perceived thing exists, even though perception does not relate [directly] to this attribute. However, since the attribute which is perceived cannot be realized without the existence of this thing, we must know that it exists. This knowledge is like the root of the knowledge of the specific essential attribute. Therefore, as we perceive [the attribute] which cannot appear in other things, we know the perceived thing, even if we do not know any [other] state of it, like [in the case of perception of] sound.(Mughnī, XII, 61–62)
Now these [necessary postulates] may be one, or they may be two or three or four or more than that… As an illustration of a single [concomitant] let it be supposed that we see smoke… We must assume the existence of the fire because of the existence of the smoke since the one can be complete (yatimm) only by means of the other. Likewise if we hear the voice of a human being from behind a wall, we must assume the existence of that human being… As an example, again, of more than one [concomitant phenomenon] that must be postulated, the following might be cited.] When, for instance, we see food go down in bulk in the belly of an animate being, and its refuse come out from it, then, unless we assume [that] four operations [were involved in the process], what has been perceived by our senses could not have been complete (yatimm)… Sometimes, too, our conviction of the reality of what we observe becomes complete (yatimm) only by the invention of a science (ṣinā‘a) that verifies it for us. We may even be compelled to resort to many such sciences.(L, 16–17; K, 18; R, 21–22)
Now all this is demonstrable only by means of the art of geometry, which shows us how one figure is subsumed under others through construction, after we have known the simples from which they are composed… We must, therefore, acknowledge all these sciences as being correct, since it is only by means of them that our conviction of the variation of the moon’s course by natural law can be complete (yatimm).(L, 18; K, 20; R, 23)
The audible things are discovered by the organ of hearing, and man testifies (shahid): this is what I have heard and none other. The same is true of the other organs of sensation. Similarly there is in the intellect a knowing force which, when confronted by intellectual matters, verifies them, so that the person becomes convinced that they are undoubtedly the concepts. According to this example all knowledge lies concealed in the intellect (maknūn fī al-‘aql); and the purpose of learning and inference (iktisāb) is only to discover it after its awakening, so that when it stands before the mind, the mind testifies concerning it that it is the truth. Therefore, this book with its speculation is intended to remind of (yunabbihū) what is in the intellect and to awaken (yuyaqqizū) what used to be neglected.
If we seek to establish the truth of [a conviction] in the domain of necessary knowledge (al-‘ilm al-ḍarūrī), we must guard it against the above-mentioned five types of vitiating factors: [a] that there is no other [means than the theory in question] of sustaining the truth of what is perceived; nor [b] any other [method ] of upholding what is known [by intellect]; [c] it must not invalidate any other truth; nor [d] must one part of it contradict another; let alone [e] that [a theory] be adopted that is worse than the one that has been rejected.[All] these [precautions are to be taken] in addition to exercising, in the determination of the sensible and the intelligible, such expert care as we have outlined before. Add to these the quality of perseverance until the art of speculation (ṣinā‘a al-naẓar) has been completed, and we have a total of seven points that must be observed to make possible for us the accurate emergence of the truth (kharajat lanā al-ḥaqīqa ṣaḥīḥatan).(L, 20; K, 22; R, 25–26) 17
Should, therefore, someone come to us with an allegation in the realm of necessary knowledge, we would test his thesis by means of these seven [criteria]. If, upon being rubbed by their touchstone and weighed by their balance, it turns out to be correct as well as acceptable, we shall make use of it. Similarly also must we proceed with the subject matters of authentic tradition—I mean the books of prophecy.(L, 20; K, 22–23; R, 26)
In this way, then—may God be merciful unto thee—do we conduct our speculation and inquiry, to the end that we may expound concretely (nukhrij ilā fi‘l) what our Master has imparted unto us by means of knowledge and necessity (bi-’l-‘ilm wa-bi-’l-ḍarūra).19 With this thesis, however, there is intimately bound up a point that we cannot avoid. It consists of the question: “… Where was the wisdom in God’s transmitting them by means of prophecy and supporting them by means of visible miraculous proofs (barāhīn al-’ayāt al-mar’iyya), rather than the intellectual ones (al-barāhīn al-‘aqliyya)?”(L, 24; K, 27; R, 31)
3. Contextual and Philosophical Explanations
- S necessarily knows that p;
- p deductively entails q, meaning that the knowledge of q is contained in the knowledge of p;
- So, S necessarily knows that q (though this knowledge could possibly be non-transparent to S).
Only those who have necessary knowledge (al-‘ilm al-iḍṭirārī al-wājib) may confirm that every [individual of the species] has the substance which the paradigm has… As for the connection based on the course of habit, there is no certain, necessary and demonstrative knowledge (ʿilm yaqīn al-wājib idtirārī burhānī) in it at all.
The point of this argument is that, if man is compounded from a single element, the syllogism necessarily (ḍarūratan) implies that he cannot feel pain, since there would be nothing that would make him feel pain… The basis of this syllogism is sensation and is a matter of consensus. Its premises follow from that basis by means of demonstration (burhān), and its conclusion follows from it by demonstration.(On the Elements, Walbridge 2014, p. 151)
There is disagreement among the ones who have knowledge: some of them said that all the knowledge [of God] is through revelation (ilhām) and did not make speculation an obligation; others said that all the knowledge occurs through a natural substratum (ṭab‘ al-maḥall) when speculating, and then obligated [people] to speculate on Him, but not in the same way we obligated.
Some responders [to the objection against speculation and inference] replied that they know that the judgment of something is necessarily the same with that of its like, and claimed that they know the truth of the inference necessarily.(K. Anwār, II 6.6)
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | As for the distinction between subjective and objective certainty in medieval philosophy, see Robert Pasnau (2017, p. 29, n. 6). |
3 | See (Al-Muqammaṣ 2016, pp. 36–37). In the context, al-Muqammaṣ provides two definitions and this is the first one. The second one defines knowledge as the soul’s apprehention of the form of the sensibles and the intelligibles, whose hylemorphic terminololy, as well as dichotomy of sensible and intelligible, has an Aristotelian overtone. |
4 | See Ibid., pp. 42–43. The concept of truth here requires more than the normal condition of correspondence between belief and fact, and seems closer to the concept of knowledge. It is noteworthy that al-Muqammaṣ follows the correspondence theory in his own definition of truth provided earlier (ibid., pp. 40–41). |
5 | For the English translation, see (trans. S. Rosenblatt) (Saadya 1948, p. 14). Hereafter, the two editions of K. al-Amānāt wa’l-I‘tiqādāt (KAI, Saadya 1880, 1970) are referred to respectively as L and K and Rosenblatt’s translation (Saadya 1948) as R. The English translation has been slightly modified. |
6 | See, e.g., (Al-Qirqisānī 1939–1943, pp. 64–71); Aaron ben Elijah, Ets Hayyim, Chapter Eighty, in Daniel Frank (1991, pp. 18–20). |
7 | In early Kalām the status of the last one is controversial. There were some theologians, like the Baghdadi school of the Mu‘tazilites, who did not accept tradition or testimony as necessary knowledge, see (Al-Baghdādī 1928, p. 12; Sklare 2021, p. 121). |
8 | Sharḥ, 50–51; Mughnī, 12: 56–66. |
9 | See, e.g., (Yūsuf al-Baṣīr 1985), Muhtawī, 2.640. |
10 | Prior Analytics, 24b18-20; Topica, 100a25-27; Metaphysics, 1015b7-9. For the medieval Arabic translation of these texts, see A. R. Badawi, Manṭiq Arsiṭū, Beirut: Dar al-qalam, 1980, pp. 142, 489; Averroes, Tafsir ma ba‘d at-tabi‘a, ed. Maurice Bouyges, Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, 1938, pp. 516–17. |
11 | KAI, L, 24; K, 27; R, 31. |
12 | In his commentary to Sefer Yetzirah, Saadya also emphasizes sense perception’s status as primary source of truth with no doubt and base the proof of the Creator on this truth, see (Saadya 1891, p. 38). |
13 | ‘Uthman, Naẓariyyat al-Taklīf, 1971, p. 60. |
14 | See (Al-Ghazālī 1962), I‘tiqād, pp. 25–26. For English translation, see Yaqub 2013, pp. 28–29. |
15 | See (Juwaynī 1950), Irshād, 1950, p. 61. For English translation, see Walker 2000, p. 36. |
16 | ʿAbd al-Jabbār, Mughnī, vol. 12, pp. 37, 42, 45, 71; for a discussion of the issue, see (Benevich 2022b, pp.12–15, 26–28). From the fact that ʿAbd al-Jabbār ascribes this position to Abū Hāshim and defends it as a reply to al-Jāḥiẓ, it is most likely to be an early Mu‘tazilite stance. |
17 | Related to this, when elaborating these conditions, Saadya uses the terms “analogy” (qiyās), “proof” (dalīl), and “inference” (istidlāl) to describe the process of approaching and weighing the alleged necessary knowledge (L, 19; K, 21; R, 24). |
18 | A similar view can be found in Ibn Taymiyya, Darʾ taʿāruḍ al-ʿaql wa-l-naql, aw Muwāfaqat ṣaḥīḥ al-manqūl li-ṣarīḥ al-maʿqūl. ed. Muḥammad Rashād Sālim. Riyadh: Dār al-Kunūz al-Adabiyya, 1979, 9:28–29. |
19 | I follow Landauer’s reading, while Kafih includes the phrase “bi-’l-ḍarūra” in the next sentence, which already has an adverbial “lā budd”. Putting a double emphasis on such a rhetorical question would be quite superfluous. |
20 | Interestingly enough, al-Fārābī’s account of certitude (yaqīn) is like a reverse image of this agenda: he insists that only demonstration and intellectual intuition can bring about absolute or necessary certitude, while admiting lesser degrees of certitude (such as non-necessary and accidental certitude) to accommodate immediate sensible abservations and testimonies as inferior forms of knowledge, in which the Kalām concept of certainty (sukūn al-nafs) is listed as “the most remote assent from certitude”, see (Black 2006, pp. 11–45). |
21 | For the “Aristotelian turn” in the Arabic reception of Hellenic sciences advocated by al-Fārābī, see (Koetschet 2022, pp. 275–76, 287). Another remarkable pre-Aristotelian-turn figure is al-Kindī who takes mathemathics represented by Euclid and Ptolemy as the scientific ideal, see (Adamson 2007, pp. 33–38; Gutas 1998, p. 120; Pasnau 2017, pp. 27, 177). |
22 | Koetschet identified this text as part of al-Rāzī’s Doubts on Galen (Koetschet 2022, pp. 282–85). The terms “necessary knowledge” appears in a context where the author elaborates three sorts of sign-inference from the manifest to the hidden (respectively based on paradigm, habit and trace-endeixis), contrasts the first two sorts with necessary knowledge, and seems to imply that the trace indicating to the nature of things has a close relation with demonstration. As for the Stoic origin of sign-inference in Kalāmic logic and its relation to Saadya, see (Van Ess 1970, pp. 26–50; Ben-Shammai 2005, p. 112, n.74). |
23 | See (Morison 2008, pp. 66–115); Hankinson, “Epistemology”, ibid., pp. 165–78. |
24 | For demonstration in Stoicism, see The Hellenistic Philosophers, ed. and trans. A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987, vol.1, pp. 213–14; R. J. Hankinson, “Stoic Epistemology”, in The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, ed. Brad Inwood, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp. 78–79, Susanne Bobzien, “Logic”, ibid., pp. 112–13; Ludwig Edelstein, The Meaning of Stoicism, London: Oxford University Press, 1966, pp. 27–28. |
25 | Efros traced Saadya’s epistemology back to Stoicism, though offering no proof but similarities (1942, pp. 136–37, 139–42, 157–58). Josef van Ess suggested the Stoic logic elements in Kalām may have originated from Greco-Roman rhetoric tradition in Late Antique and Early Islam, but also admitted that the legacy of the latter is a synthesis of different schools and thus not distinctly Stoic (Van Ess 1970, pp. 32–33). |
26 | See (Saadya 1894, p. 127); L, pp. 73, 77; K, pp. 76, 80; R, pp. 87, 92. The tenth century Jewish thinker Abū al-Khayr’s statement may echo this thesis: “[The knowledge of God] is necessary from the perspective of the intellect, and inferential from the perspective of the sense perception.” (al-Tawḥīdī, al-Muqābasāt, ed. M. Hussein, Tehran: Markaz Nashar Daneshgahi, 1987, p. 174). |
27 | |
28 | For the analytical empiricism in Kalām and its “eastern” (Central Asian and Indian) origins, see (Dong 2018). I borrowed the term from Hao Wang, see (Wang 1985). By analytical empiricism, I mean an epistemological position holding that knowledge is primarily sense perception and conceptual knowledge is all but a conventional ordering of perceptions. In contrast, intellectualism refers to the stance that knowledge can only be attained by the intellect, while perceptions are no knowledge in its true sense but at most its raw materials. |
29 | Bilal Ibrahim characterized Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī’s alternative programme to the Aristotelian–Avicennian essentialist science as phenomenalism, see (Ibrahim 2013a, pp. 379–431); Benevich analyzed the arguments of al-Rāzī, al-Suhrawardī, and Abū l-Barakat al-Baghdadī against Peripatetic scientific definition and identified their epistemological approach as a “unified direct realism”, see (Benevich 2022a, pp. 72–108). We do not suggest that al-Rāzī was under the influence of Saadya (for it is unlikely for any major medieval Musilim authors like al-Rāzī to have access to the Jewish Kalām works), but just intend to point to the common cause and approach shared by these two thinkers. A comparative research of Saadya’s and al-Rāzī’s (and possibly others’) projects of the scientific ideal is in order, and yet goes beyond the scope of this study. |
References
- Abrahamov, Binyamin. 1993. Necessary Knowledge in Islamic Theology. British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies 20: 20–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adamson, Peter. 2007. Al-Kindī. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Baghdādī. 1928. K. Usūl al-Dīn. Istanbul: Dar al-Funun al-Turkiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Ghazālī. 1962. I‘tiqād, Ankara: Nur Matbaasi; English translation, A. M. Yaqub, trans. 2013. Moderation in Belief. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Muqammaṣ. 2016. ‘Ishrūn Maqāla. Translated and Edited by Sarah Stroumsa. Provo: Young Brigham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Qirqisānī. 1918. Tafsīr Bereshit. In Qirqisāni Studies. Edited by H. Hirschfeld. London: Jews’ College, pp. 39–59. [Google Scholar]
- Al-Qirqisānī. 1939–1943. K. Anwār. Edited by Leon Nemoy. New York: Alexander Kohut Memorial Foundation. [Google Scholar]
- ‘Abd al-Jabbār. 1960–1965. Mughnī. Edited by Taha Husayn. Cairo: Al-Dar al-Mijriyah li-’l-Ta’lif wa-al-Tarjamah. [Google Scholar]
- ‘Abd al-Jabbār, Ahmad ibn al-Husayn Mānakdīm. 1996. Sharh al-Usūl al-Khamsa. Edited by A. K.‘Uthmān. Cairo: Maktaba Wahība. [Google Scholar]
- Benevich, Fedor. 2022a. Meaning and Definition: Scepticism and Semantics in Twelfth-Century Arabic Philosophy. Theoria 88: 72–108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benevich, Fedor. 2022b. Knowledge as a Mental State in Muʿtazilite Kalām. Oriens 50: 244–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ben-Shammai, Haggai. 1977. (Hebrew) The Doctrines of Religious Thought of Abû Yûsuf Ya’qûb al-Qirqisânî and Yefet ben ‘Elî. Ph.D. thesis, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem, Israel. [Google Scholar]
- Ben-Shammai, Haggai. 2005. Kalām in Medieval Jewish Philosophy. In History of Jewish Philosophy. Edited by Daniel Frank and Oliver Leaman. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Black, Deborah. 2006. Knowledge and Certitude in al-Fārābī’s Epistemology. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 16: 11–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Davidson, Herbert A. 1987. Proofs for Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dong, Xiuyuan. 2018. The Presence of Buddhist Thought in Kalām Literature. Philosophy East and West 68: 944–73. [Google Scholar]
- Efros, Israel. 1942. Saadia’s Theory of Knowledge. The Jewish Quarterly Review 33: 133–70. [Google Scholar]
- Frank, Daniel. 1991. The Religious Philosophy of the Karaite Aaron ben Elijah: The Problem of Divine Justice. Ph.D. dissertation, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA. [Google Scholar]
- Frank, Richard. 1971. Several Fundamental Assumptions of the Baṣra School of the Mu’tazila. Studia Islamica 33: 5–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Galen. 1916. On the Natural Faculties. Edited by Georg Helmreich. Translated by Arthur Brock. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 274–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 1998. Greek Thought, Arabic Culture. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Hegedus, Gyongyi. 2013. Saadya Gaon: The Double Path of the Mystic and the Rationalist. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn, Mattawayh. 2009. Al-Tadhkira fī Ahkām al-Jawāhir wa-l-a‘rād. Edited by Daniel Gimaret. Cairo: Institut Français D’archéologie Orientale. [Google Scholar]
- Ibrahim, Bilal. 2013a. Fahr al-Din al-Razi, Ibn al-Haytam and Aristotelian Science: Essentialism Versus Phenomenalism in Post-Classical Islamic Thought. Oriens 41: 379–431. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ibrahim, Mohd Radhi. 2013b. Immediate Knowledge according to al-Qāḍī ‘Abd al-Jabbār. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 23: 101–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Juwaynī. 1950. Irshād. Cairo: Maktaba al-Khaniji, (English translation, P. Walker, trans. 2000. A Guide to Conclusive Proofs for the Principles of Belief. Reading: Garnet Publishing). [Google Scholar]
- Koetschet, Pauline. 2022. What Level of Certainty Can Medical Sign-Inference Reach? A Discussion of Galen’s Demonstrative Method in the Islamic World. In Galen’s Epistemology. Edited by Robert J. Hankinson and Matyáš Havrda. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 275–89. [Google Scholar]
- Kraus, Paul. 1935. Jabbir Ibn Hayyan, Volume 1: Textes Choisis. Cairo: Librairie el-Khandgi. [Google Scholar]
- Lobel, Diana. 2000. Between Mysticism and Philosophy: Sufi Language of Religious Experience in Judah Ha-Levi’s Kuzari. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Maimonides. 1963. The Guide of the Perplexed. Translated by Shlomo Pines. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Morison, Ben. 2008. Logic. In Cambridge Companion to Galen. Edited by R. J. Hankinson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 66–115. [Google Scholar]
- Pasnau, Robert. 2017. After Certainty: A History of Our Epistemic Ideals and Illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peters, Johannes Reinier Theodorus Maria. 1976. God’s Created Speech: A Study in The Speculative Theology of The Muʿtazili Qadi l-Qudat Abul-Hasan ʿAbd al-Jabbar ibn Ahmad al-Hamadhani. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1880. K. al-Amānāt wa’l-I‘tiqādāt. Edited by Samuel Landauer. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1891. Commentaire sur le Séfer Yesira, ou Livre de la Creation. Translated and Edited by Mayer Lambert. Paris: É. Bouillon. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1894. Version Arabes des Proverbes. Translated and Edited by Joseph Derenbourg, and Mayer Lambert. Paris: Libraire de la Societe Asiatique. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1899. Version Arabes du livre de Job. Translated and Edited by Wilhelm Bacher, Joseph Derenbourg, and Hartwig Derenbourg. Paris: Libraire de la Societe Asiatique. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1970. K. al-Amānāt wa’l-I‘tiqādāt. Edited by Josef Kafih. Jerusalem: Sura. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1973. Iyov ‘im Targum ve-Perush ha-Gaon Rabbenu Saadya ben Yosef Fayyumi. Edited by Josef Kafih. Jerusalem: Sura. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1948. The Book of Beliefs and Opinions. Translated by Samuel Rosenblatt. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Saadya. 1988. The Book of Theodicy: Translation and Commentary on the Book of Job by Saadiah ben Joseph al-Fayyūmī. Translated by Lenn E. Goodman. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sklare, David. 2021. Epistemology in the Service of Polemic: Yūsuf al-Baṣīr’s Kitāb al-Isti‘ānah: Text and Translation. In Polemical and Exegetical Polarities in Medieval Jewish Cultures: Studies in Honour of Daniel J. Lasker. Edited by Ehud Krinis, Nabih Bashir, Sara Offenberg and Shalom Sadik. Berlin: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Stroumsa, Sarah. 2002. Saadiah Gaon: A Jewish Thinker in a Mediterranean Society. In Jewish Culture in Muslim Lands and Cairo Geniza Studies. Edited by M. A. Friedman. Tel-Aviv: Tel Aviv University, pp. 7–42. [Google Scholar]
- Vajda, Georges. 1948. Études sur Saadia. Revue des Études Juives 109: 68–102. [Google Scholar]
- Van Ess, Josef. 1970. The Logical Structure of Islamic Theology. In Logic in Classical Islamic Culture. Edited by Gustave E. von Grunebaum. Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, pp. 21–50. [Google Scholar]
- Walbridge, John. 2014. The Alexandrian Epitomes of Galen, Volume 1: On the Medical Sects for Beginners; The Small Art of Medicine; On the Elements According to the Opinion of Hippocrates. Provo: Brigham Young University Press Utah. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Hao. 1985. Two Commandments of Analytic Empiricism. The Journal of Philosophy 82: 449–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wisnovsky, Robert. 2003. Avicenna’s Metaphysics in Context. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wisnovsky, Robert. 2012. Essence and Existence in the Eleventh-and Twelfth-Century Islamic East: A Sketch. In The Arabic, Hebrew and Latin reception of Avicenna’s Metaphysics. Edited by Dag Nikolaus Hasse and Amos Bertolacci. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Harry Austryn. 1942. The Double Faith Theory in Clement, Saadia, Averroes and St. Thomas, and Its Origin in Aristotle and the Stoics. The Jewish Quarterly Review 33: 213–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yūsuf, al-Baṣīr. 1985. Muhtawī. Edited by Georges Vajda and David R. Blumenthal. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Dong, X.; Memet-Ali, A.-S. Saadya on Necessary Knowledge. Religions 2025, 16, 453. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040453
Dong X, Memet-Ali A-S. Saadya on Necessary Knowledge. Religions. 2025; 16(4):453. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040453
Chicago/Turabian StyleDong, Xiuyuan, and Abd-Salam Memet-Ali. 2025. "Saadya on Necessary Knowledge" Religions 16, no. 4: 453. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040453
APA StyleDong, X., & Memet-Ali, A.-S. (2025). Saadya on Necessary Knowledge. Religions, 16(4), 453. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040453