Equivalence Principle in Classical and Quantum Gravity
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Equivalence Principle in General Relativity
The equations of motion for matter coupled to gravity remain locally identical to the equations of motion for matter in the absence of gravity.
- When comparing the equations of motion in the presence and in the absence of gravity, the claim that they remain identical may naively suggest that gravity does not influence the motion of matter in any way whatsoever. However, on closer inspection, the statement is that the two sets of equations remain locally identical, emphasising that the notion of locality is a crucial feature of the EP. While equations of motion are already local in nature (since they are usually expressed as partial differential equations of finite order), the actual interaction between matter and gravity enters only when integrating those equations to find a solution (see Appendix A for a detailed example).
- In order to compare the equations of motion for matter in the presence of gravity to those in its absence, the equations themselves need to be put in a suitable form (typically expressed in general curvilinear coordinates, as tensor equations). The statement of EP relies on a theorem that this can always be achieved, first noted by Erich Kretschmann [54].
- Despite being dominantly a statement about the interaction between matter and gravity, EP also implicitly suggests that the best way to describe the gravitational field is as a property of the geometry of spacetime, such as its metric [55]. In that setup, EP can be reformulated as a statement of minimal coupling between gravity and matter, stating that equations of motion for matter may depend on the spacetime metric and its first derivatives, but not on its (antisymmetrised) second derivatives, i.e., the spacetime curvature does not explicitly appear in the equations of motion for matter.
- The generalisation of EP to other gauge fields is completely straightforward, by replacing the role of gravity with some other gauge field, and suitably redefining what matter is. For example, in electrodynamics, the EP can be formulated as follows:
The equations of motion for matter coupled to the electromagnetic field remain locally identical to the equations of motion for matter in the absence of the electromagnetic field.
- This statement can also be suitably reformulated as the minimal coupling between the electromagnetic (EM) field and matter, i.e., coupling matter to the electromagnetic potential but not to the corresponding field strength . This is in fact the standard way the EM field is coupled to matter (see Appendix A for an illustrative example). Even more generally, the gauge field sector of the whole Standard Model of elementary particles (SM) is built using the minimal coupling prescription, meaning that the suitably generalised version of the EP actually prescribes the interaction between matter and all fundamental interactions in nature, namely strong, weak, electromagnetic and gravitational. In this sense, EP is a cornerstone principle for the whole fundamental physics, as we understand it today.
- Equality of gravitational and inertial mass. This is one of the oldest variants of EP, going back to Newton’s law of universal gravitation. The statement claims that the “gravitational charge” of a body is the same as the body’s resistance to acceleration, in the sense that the mass appearing on the left-hand side of Newton’s second law of motion exactly cancels the mass appearing in Newton’s gravitational force law on the right-hand side. This allows one to relate it to the modern version of EP, in the sense that a suitably accelerated observer could rewrite Newton’s law of motion as the equation for a free particle, exploiting the cancellation of the “intertial force” and the gravitational force on the right-hand side of the equation. Unfortunately, this version of EP is intrinsically nonrelativistic, and applicable only in the context of Newtonian gravity since already in GR the source of gravity becomes the full stress-energy tensor of matter fields, rather than just the total mass. Finally, this principle obviously fails when applied to photons, as demonstrated by the gravitational bending of light.
- Universality of free fall. Going back all the way to Galileo, this statement claims that the interaction between matter and gravity does not depend on any intrinsic property of matter itself, such as its mass, angular momentum, chemical composition, temperature, or any other property, leading to the idea that gravity couples universally (i.e., in the same way) to all matter. Formulated from experimental observations by Galileo, its validity is related to the quality of experiments used to verify it. As we shall see below, in a precise enough setting, one can experimentally observe direct coupling between the angular momentum of a body and spacetime curvature [32,33,34,35,36,37,38,39,40,41,42,43,44,45,46], invalidating the statement.
- Local equality between gravity and inertia. Often called Einstein’s equivalence principle, the statement claims that a local and suitably isolated observer cannot distinguish between accelerating and being at rest in a uniform gravitational field. While this statement is much closer in spirit to the modern formulation of EP, it obscures the crucial aspect of the principle — coupling of matter to gravity. Namely, in this formulation, it is merely implicit that the only way an observer can attempt to distinguish gravity from inertia is by making local experiments using some form of matter, i.e., studying the equations of motion of matter in the two situations and trying to distinguish them by observing whether or not matter behaves differently. Moreover, the statement is often discussed in the context of mechanics, arguing that any given particle does not distinguish between gravity and inertia. This has two main pitfalls—first, the reliance on particles is very misleading (as we will discuss below in much more detail), and second, it implicitly suggests that gravity and inertia are the same phenomenon, which is completely false. Namely, inertia can be understood as a specific form of gravity, but a general gravitational field cannot be simulated by inertia, since inertia cannot account for tidal effects of inhomogeneous configurations of gravity.
- Weak equivalence principle. Stating that the equations of motion of particles do not depend on spacetime curvature, or equivalently, that the motion of a free particle is always a geodesic trajectory in spacetime, WEP is in fact an application of modern EP to mechanical point-like particles (i.e., test particles). One can argue that, as far as the notion of a point-like particle is a well-defined concept in physics, WEP is a good principle. Nevertheless, as we will discuss below in detail, the notion of a point-like particle is an idealisation that does not actually have any counterpart in reality, in either classical or quantum physics. Regarding a realistic particle (with nonzero size), WEP never holds, due to the explicit effect of gravitational tidal forces across the particle’s size. In this sense, WEP can be considered at best an approximate principle, which can be assumed to hold only in situations where particle size can be approximated to zero.
- Strong equivalence principle. This version of the principle states that the equations of motion of all fundamental fields in nature do not depend on spacetime curvature (see [55], Section 16.2, page 387). To the best of our knowledge so far, fields are indeed the most fundamental building blocks in modern physics (such as SM), while the strength of the gravitational field is indeed described by spacetime curvature (as in GR). In this sense, the statement of SEP is actually an instance of EP applied to field theory, and as such equivalent to the modern statement of EP. So far, all our knowledge of natural phenomena is consistent with the validity of SEP.
3. The Notion of Trajectory in Classical and Quantum Mechanics
4. The Notion of a Particle in Field Theory
- It is an eigenstate of the particle number operator for the eigenvalue 1.
- It has a sharp value of the momentum , and corresponds to a completely delocalised plane wave configuration of the field.
- It has no centre of mass, and no concept of “position” in space since the “position operator” is not a well-defined concept for the field.
- States of this kind are said to describe elementary particles, understood as asymptotic free states of past and future infinity, in the context of the S-matrix for scattering processes. An example of a real scalar particle of this type would be the Higgs particle. For fields of other types (Dirac fields, vector fields, etc.) examples would be an electron, a photon, a neutrino, an asymptotically free quark, and so on. Essentially, all particles tabulated in the Standard Model of elementary particles are of this type.
- It is not an eigenstate of the particle number operator, and the expectation value of this operator is typically different from 1.
- It is usually well localised in space, and does not have a sharp value of momentum.
- As long as the kink maintains a stable configuration (i.e., as long as it does not decay), one can in principle assign to it the concept of size, and as a consequence also the concepts of centre of mass, position in space, and trajectory. In this sense, a kink can play the role of a test particle.
- States of this kind are said to describe composite particles. Given an interacting theory such as the Standard Model, under certain circumstances quarks and gluons form bound states called a proton and a neutron. Moreover, protons and neutrons further form bound states called atomic nuclei, which together with electrons and photons form atoms, molecules, and so on.
5. Conclusions and Discussion
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A
Appendix A.1. The Gravitational Case
Appendix A.2. The Electromagnetic Case
Appendix A.3. The Test Particle Case
References
- Kay, B.S. Decoherence of macroscopic closed systems within Newtonian quantum gravity. Class. Quantum Gravity 1998, 15, L89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oniga, T.; Wang, C.H.T. Quantum gravitational decoherence of light and matter. Phys. Rev. D 2016, 93, 044027. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bruschi, D.E. On the weight of entanglement. Phys. Lett. B 2016, 754, 182. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bose, S.; Mazumdar, A.; Morley, G.W.; Ulbricht, H.; Toroš, M.; Paternostro, M.; Geraci, A.A.; Barker, P.F.; Kim, M.S.; Milburn, G. Spin entanglement witness for quantum gravity. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2017, 119, 240401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Marletto, C.; Vedral, V. Gravitationally Induced Entanglement between Two Massive Particles is Sufficient Evidence of Quantum Effects in Gravity. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2017, 119, 240402. [Google Scholar]
- Marletto, C.; Vedral, V. When can gravity path-entangle two spatially superposed masses? Phys. Rev. D 2018, 98, 046001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Paunković, N.; Vojinović, M. Gauge protected entanglement between gravity and matter. Class. Quantum Gravity 2018, 35, 185015. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Oreshkov, O.; Costa, F.; Brukner, Č. Quantum correlations with no causal order. Nat. Commun. 2012, 3, 1092. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Araújo, M.; Branciard, C.; Costa, F.; Feix, A.; Giarmatzi, C.; Brukner, Č. Witnessing causal nonseparability. New J. Phys. 2015, 17, 102001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vilasini, V. An Introduction to Causality in Quantum Theory (and Beyond). Master’s Thesis, ETH, Zürich, Switzerland, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Oreshkov, O. Time-delocalized quantum subsystems and operations: On the existence of processes with indefinite causal structure in quantum mechanics. Quantum 2019, 3, 206. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Paunković, N.; Vojinović, M. Causal orders, quantum circuits and spacetime: Distinguishing between definite and superposed causal orders. Quantum 2020, 4, 275. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vilasini, V.; Colbeck, R. General framework for cyclic and fine-tuned causal models and their compatibility with space-time. Phys. Rev. A 2022, 106, 032204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vilasini, V.; Renner, R. Embedding cyclic causal structures in acyclic spacetimes: No-go results for process matrices. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2203.11245. [Google Scholar]
- Ormrod, N.; Vanrietvelde, A.; Barrett, J. Causal structure in the presence of sectorial constraints, with application to the quantum switch. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2204.10273. [Google Scholar]
- Giacomini, F.; Castro-Ruiz, E.; Brukner, Č. Quantum mechanics and the covariance of physical laws in quantum reference frames. Nat. Commun. 2019, 10, 494. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Vanrietvelde, A.; Höhn, P.A.; Giacomini, F.; Castro-Ruiz, E. A change of perspective: Switching quantum reference frames via a perspective-neutral framework. Quantum 2020, 4, 225. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Krumm, M.; Höhn, P.A.; Müller, M.P. Quantum reference frame transformations as symmetries and the paradox of the third particle. Quantum 2021, 5, 530. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ahmad, S.A.; Galley, T.D.; Höhn, P.A.; Lock, M.P.E.; Smith, A.R.H. Quantum Relativity of Subsystems. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2022, 128, 170401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- de la Hamette, A.C.; Kabel, V.; Castro-Ruiz, E.; Brukner, Č. Falling through masses in superposition: Quantum reference frames for indefinite metrics. arXiv 2021, arXiv:2112.11473. [Google Scholar]
- Colladay, D.; Kostelecký, V.A. Lorentz-violating extension of the standard model. Phys. Rev. D 1998, 58, 116002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Kostelecký, V.A.; Russell, N. Data tables for Lorentz and CPT violation. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2011, 83, 11–31. [Google Scholar]
- Amelino-Camelia, G. Particle-dependent deformations of Lorentz symmetry. Symmetry 2012, 4, 344–378. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Amelino-Camelia, G.; Palmisano, M.; Ronco, M.; D’Amico, G. Mixing coproducts for theories with particle-dependent relativistic properties. Int. J. Mod. Phys. D 2020, 29, 2050017. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Torri, M.D.C.; Antonelli, V.; Miramonti, L. Homogeneously Modified Special relativity (HMSR). Eur. Phys. J. C 2019, 79, 808. [Google Scholar]
- Pipa, F.; Paunković, N.; Vojinović, M. Entanglement-induced deviation from the geodesic motion in quantum gravity. J. Cosmol. Astropart. Phys. 2019, 2019, 57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Giacomini, F.; Brukner, Č. Einstein’s Equivalence principle for superpositions of gravitational fields. arXiv 2020, arXiv:2012.13754. [Google Scholar]
- Giacomini, F.; Brukner, Č. Quantum superposition of spacetimes obeys Einstein’s equivalence principle. AVS Quantum Sci. 2022, 4, 015601. [Google Scholar]
- Marletto, C.; Vedral, V. On the testability of the equivalence principle as a gauge principle detecting the gravitational t3 phase. Front. Phys. 2020, 8, 176. [Google Scholar]
- Marletto, C.; Vedral, V. Sagnac interferometer and the quantum nature of gravity. J. Phys. Commun. 2021, 5, 051001. [Google Scholar]
- Marletto, C.; Vedral, V. The quantum totalitarian property and exact symmetries. AVS Quantum Sci. 2022, 4, 015603. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Einstein, A.; Infeld, L.; Hoffmann, B. The Gravitational Equations and the Problem of Motion. Ann. Math. 1938, 39, 65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mathisson, M. Neue mechanik materieller systemes. Acta Phys. Pol. 1937, 6, 163. [Google Scholar]
- Papapetrou, A. Spinning test-particles in general relativity, I. Proc. R. Soc. A 1951, 209, 248. [Google Scholar]
- Tulczyjev, W. Equations of motion of rotating bodies in general relativity theory. Acta Phys. Pol. 1959, 18, 393. [Google Scholar]
- Taub, A.H. Motion of Test Bodies in General Relativity. J. Math. Phys. 1964, 5, 112. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dixon, G. A covariant multipole formalism for extended test bodies in general relativity. Nuovo Cim. 1964, 34, 317. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dixon, G. Classical theory of charged particles with spin and the classical limit of the Dirac equation. Nuovo Cim. 1965, 38, 1616. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dixon, G. Dynamics of extended bodies in general relativity. I. Momentum and angular momentum. Proc. R. Soc. A 1970, 314, 499. [Google Scholar]
- Dixon, G. Dynamics of extended bodies in general relativity - II. Moments of the charge-current vector. Proc. R. Soc. A 1970, 319, 509. [Google Scholar]
- Dixon, G. The definition of multipole moments for extended bodies. Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 1973, 4, 199. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yasskin, P.B.; Stoeger, W.R. Propagation equations for test bodies with spin and rotation in theories of gravity with torsion. Phys. Rev. D 1980, 21, 2081. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nomura, K.; Shirafuji, T.; Hayashi, K. Spinning Test Particles in Spacetime with Torsion. Prog. Theor. Phys. 1991, 86, 1239. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nomura, K.; Shirafuji, T.; Hayashi, K. Semiclassical particles with arbitrary spin in the Riemann-Cartan space-time. Prog. Theor. Phys. 1992, 87, 1275. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vasilić, M.; Vojinović, M. Classical spinning branes in curved backgrounds. JHEP 2007, 7, 28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Vasilić, M.; Vojinović, M. Spinning branes in Riemann-Cartan spacetime. Phys. Rev. D 2008, 78, 104002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Accioly, A.; Paszko, R. Conflict between the Classical Equivalence Principle and Quantum Mechanics. Adv. Stud. Theor. Phys. 2009, 3, 65. [Google Scholar]
- Longhi, S. Equivalence principle and quantum mechanics: Quantum simulation with entangled photons. Opt. Lett. 2018, 43, 226. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Chowdhury, P.; Home, D.; Majumdar, A.S.; Mousavi, S.V.; Mozaffari, M.R.; Sinha, S. Strong quantum violation of the gravitational weak equivalence principle by a non-Gaussian wave packet. Class. Quantum Gravity 2012, 29, 025010. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rosi, G.; D’Amico, G.; Cacciapuoti, L.; Sorrentino, F.; Prevedelli, M.; Zych, M.; Brukner, Č.; Tino, G.M. Quantum test of the equivalence principle for atoms in coherent superposition of internal energy states. Nat. Commun. 2017, 8, 15529. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Zych, M.; Brukner, Č. Quantum formulation of the Einstein Equivalence Principle. Nat. Phys. 2018, 14, 1027. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Anastopoulos, C.; Hu, B.L. Equivalence principle for quantum systems: Dephasing and phase shift of free-falling particles. Class. Quantum Gravity 2018, 35, 035011. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hardy, L. Implementation of the Quantum Equivalence Principle. In Progress and Visions in Quantum Theory in View of Gravity; Finster, F., Giulini, D., Kleiner, J., Tolksdorf, J., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2020; pp. 189–220. [Google Scholar]
- Kretschmann, E. Über den physikalischen Sinn der Relativitätspostulate, A. Einsteins neue und seine ursprüngliche Relativitätstheorie. Ann. Phys. 1918, 358, 575–614. [Google Scholar]
- Misner, C.W.; Thorne, K.S.; Wheeler, J.A. Gravitation; W. H. Freeman and Co.: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Okon, E.; Callender, C. Does Quantum Mechanics Clash with the Equivalence Principle—And Does it Matter? Eur. J. Phil. Sci. 2011, 1, 133. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Casola, E.D.; Liberati, S.; Sonego, S. Nonequivalence of equivalence principles. Am. J. Phys. 2015, 83, 39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Viola, L.; Onofrio, R. Testing the equivalence principle through freely falling quantum objects. Phys. Rev. D 1997, 55, 455–462. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plyatsko, R. Gravitational ultrarelativistic spin-orbit interaction and the weak equivalence principle. Phys. Rev. D 1998, 58, 084031. [Google Scholar]
- Bose, S.; Mazumdar, A.; Schut, M.; Toroš, M. Entanglement witness for the weak equivalence principle. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2203.11628. [Google Scholar]
- Blagojević, M. Gravitation and Gauge Symmetries; Institute of Physics Publishing: Bristol, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Landau, L.D.; Lifshitz, E.M. The Classical Theory of Fields, 4th ed.; Butterworth-Heinemann: Oxford, UK, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Peskin, M.E.; Schroeder, D.V. An Introduction to Quantum Field Theory; Addison-Wesley Publishing Co.: Boston, MA, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Paunković, N.; Vojinović, M. Equivalence Principle in Classical and Quantum Gravity. Universe 2022, 8, 598. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8110598
Paunković N, Vojinović M. Equivalence Principle in Classical and Quantum Gravity. Universe. 2022; 8(11):598. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8110598
Chicago/Turabian StylePaunković, Nikola, and Marko Vojinović. 2022. "Equivalence Principle in Classical and Quantum Gravity" Universe 8, no. 11: 598. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8110598
APA StylePaunković, N., & Vojinović, M. (2022). Equivalence Principle in Classical and Quantum Gravity. Universe, 8(11), 598. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8110598